Inference to the Best Explanation: A Model for Rational Choice of Logical Theories

Document Type : Research Paper

Authors

1 PhD candidate of logic, Department of Philosophy, University of Isfahan,

2 Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Isfahan

Abstract

Since the emergence of non-classical logics in the twentieth century, the assumption that logical knowledge is a priori has been challenged. Currently, logicians speak of preferring one logical theory over another and presenting a model of rational choice. “Inference to the best explanation” is a proposed model for the rational selection among scientific theories, and in this paper, we show that logical theories have the necessary features to apply such a methodology in the field of logic. Particularly, we show that such preferential treatment is not merely a liberal choice of a logical language, as Carnap supposed, but the inconsistency with some accepted evidence leads logicians to choose a logic theory that is compatible with that evidence. The Meaning variances of the logical constants are one of the issues that challenge the commensurability of logic theories. Having explained different solutions to this problem, we try to defend the best one in a way that avoids criticism.

Keywords


[1] Birkhoff, G., and von Neumann, J. (1936), ‘The Logic of Quantum Mechanics’, Annals of Mathematics, 37: 823–43.
[2] Boghossian, P. (2003). Blind reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Vol 77:225–248.
[3] Carnap, R. (1937). The logical syntax of language. London: Routledge.
[4] Dummett, M. (1973a). “Is Logic empirical?” In Truth and Other Enigmas, edited by M. Dummett, 269–289. Duckworth.
[5] Dummett, M. (1973b). “The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionistic Logic.” In Truth and Other Enigmas, edited by M. Dummett, 215–247. Duckworth.
[6] Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox, OUP
[7] Field, Hartry. (2015). What is validity. In C. R. Caret, O. Hjortland (eds), Foundation of logical consequence. Oxford University Press.
[8] Frege, G. (1982). The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System. Translated by Montgomery Furth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
[9] Gentzen, G. (1934). Untersuchungen ¨uber das logische Schliessen. Math. Zeitschrift, 39:405–431. Translated in The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, ed. by M. E. Szabo. North Holland, 1969.
[10] Hjortland, O. T. (2014). Verbal disputes in logic: Against minimalism for logical connectives. Logique et Analyse, 227:463–486.
[11] Kuhn,T.(1962). The structure of scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago press.
[12] Murzi, J , Cararra, M. (2014). More reflections on consequence, logique and Analysis vol 227, pp.2223-258
[13] Prawitz, D. (1977). Meaning and proofs: on the conflict between classical and intuitionistic logic. Theoria,43:2–40.
[14] Priest, G. (1989a). Classical Logic Aufgehoben’, in Priest, Routley, and Norman, ch. 4.
[15] Priest, G. (2006a). Doubt Truth to be a Liar. OUP, Oxford.
[16] Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to Non-classical logic, Cambridge university press.
[17] Priest, G. (2014). Revising Logic. In P. Rush (ed), The Metaphysic of Logic, Cambridge university press
[18] Priest, G.(2002b) ‘Paraconsistent Logic’, in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 2nd edition, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, vi. 287–393.
[19] Putnam, H. (2002). The collapse of fact/value dichotomy. Harvard university press.
[20] Quine,W,O . (1970). Philosophy of logic, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall
[21] Quinne,W.O.(1961). Two Dogmas of Empiricism. in From a Logical Point of View, second, revised, edition , Harvard University Press
[22] Resnik, M. (1985). Logic: Normative or Descriptive? The Ethics of Belief or a Branch of Psychology? Philosophy of Science, Vol. 52, No. 2 (Jun., 1985), pp. 221-238
[23] Williamson, T. (2015). Semantic paradoxes and abductive methdology. In Armour-Garb, B., editor,The Relevance of the Liar. OUP, Oxford.